Skip to main content

Full text of "The philosophy of Bergson"

See other formats


2430 
B4Z7r 


A 

A 

o 
o 

0 
9 

- 

SOL 

III 

ITHERN 

REGIO 

3 

NAL 

9 

^^_ _JC 

o 

__^^_ ;  jg 

7 

RYI 

2 

:ACI 

III 

LIT' 

5 

RUSSELL 

PHILOSOPHY  OF  B£RGSON 


THE  LIBRARY 

OF 

THE  UNIVERSITY 

OF  CALIFORNIA 

LOS  ANGELES 


THE 


HILOSOPHY  OF  BERGSON 


BY   THE 

Hon.  Bertrand  Russell 

IRER    AND    LATE    FELLOW   OF   TRINITY   COLLEGE,    CAMBRIDGE 


WITH    A     REPLY 

BY 

Mr.  H.   WILDON   CARR 

SECRETARY    OF    THE    ARISTOTELIAN    SOCIETY 

AND     A      REJOINDER     BY     MR.     RUSSELL 


Published  for  "The  Heretics"  by 

BOWES    AND    BOWES 

Cambridge 

London :    Macmilian  and  Co-,  Ltd. 

Glasgow ;    Jas.  MacLehose  and  Sons 

iou 


Price  ONE  SHILLING  Net. 


THE 

PHILOSOPHY  OF  BERQSON 


BY    THE 

Hon.  Bertrand  Russell 

LECTURER    AND    LATE    FELLOW   OF   TRINITY    COLLEGE,    CAMBRIDGE 


WITH     A     REPLY 

BY 

Mr.   H.    WILDON    CARR 

SECRETARY    OF    THE    ARISTOTELIAN    SOCIETY 

AND     A      REJOINDER     BY     MR.     RUSSELL 


Published  for  "The  Heretics"  by 
BOWES    AND    BOWES 

Cambridge 

London  :    Macmillan  and  Co.,  Ltd. 

Qlasgow  :    Jas.  MacLehose  and  Sons 

1914 


Mr.  Russell's  criticism  of  M.  Bergson  was  read  before  "  The 
Heretics,"  in  Trinity  College,  on  March  nth,  1913,  and  was 
afterwards  published  in  The  Monist,  July,  1912. 

Mr.  Carr's  reply,  and  Mr.  Russell's  rejoinder,  appeared  in 
The  Cambridge  Magazine  for  April  12th  and  April  26th, 
1913,  respectively. 

The  Society  is  indebted  to  the  editors  of  both  papers  for 
permission  to  republish. 

With  regard  to  the  value  of  the  following  pages  as  an 
authoritative  account  of  two  of  the  leading  tendencies  in  modern 
philosophic  thought,  it  is  perhaps  worth  while  to  record  that  M. 
Bergson  wrote  to  the  Editor  of  The  Cambridge  Magazine,  in 
reply  to  a  request  that  he  should  contribute  to  the  discussion 
himself : — 

"  Je  trouve  excellente  la  reponse  que  Mr.  Wildon  Carr  a 
deja  faite,  et  qui  porte  sur  les  points  speciaux  vises  par  la  critique 
de  Mr.  Russell." 


THE    PHILOSOPHY 
OF    BERGSON.* 


The  classification  of  philosophies  is  effected,  as  a  rule, 
either  by  their  methods  or  by  their  lesults  :  "empirical" 
and  "  a  priori  "  is  a  classification  by  methods,  "  realist  "  and 
"  idealist  "  is  a  classification  by  results.  An  attempt  to 
classify  Bergson's  philosophy  in  either  of  these  ways  is  hardly 
likely  to  be  successful,  since  it  cuts  across  all  the  recognised 
divisions. 

But  there  is  another  way  of  classifying  philosophies, 
less  precise,  but  perhaps  more  helpful  to  the  non-philo- 
sophical ;  in  this  way,  the  principle  of  division  is  according 
to  the  predominant  desire  which  has  led  the  philosopher 
to  philosophize.  Thus  we  shall  have  philosophies  of  feeling 
inspired  by  the  love  of  happiness  ;  theoretical  philosophies, 
inspired  by  the  love  of  knowledge  ;  and  practical  philosophies, 
inspired  by  the  love  of  action. 

Among  philosophies  of  feeling  we  shall  place  all  those 
which  are  primarily  optimistic  or  pessimistic,  all  those  that 
offer  schemes  of  salvation  or  try  to  prove  that  salvation  is 
impossible  ;  to  this  class  belong  most  religious  philosophies. 
Among  theoretical  philosophies  we  shall  place  most  of  the 


*  The  abbreviations  of  the  titles  of  the  works  of  M.  Bergson  referred 
to  are  :  C.  E.,  Creative  Evolution  ;  M.  and  M.,  Matter  and  Memo-\  ;  T  . 
and  F.  W.,  Time  and  Free  Will.  The  references  are  to  tb.5  English 
translations  of  M.  Bergson's  books. 


great  systems  ;  for  though  the  desire  for  knowledge  is  rare, 
it  has  been  the  source  of  most  of  what  is  best  in  philosophy. 
Practical  philosophies,  on  the  other  hand,  will  be  those  which 
regard  action  as  the  supreme  good,  considering  happiness 
an  effect  and  knowledge  a  mere  instrument  of  successful 
activity.  Philosophies  of  this  type  would  have  been  common 
among  Western  Europeans  if  philosophers  had  been  average 
men  ;  as  it  is,  they  have  been  rare  until  recent  times,  in  fact 
their  chief  representatives  are  the  pragmatists  and  M.  Bergson. 
In  the  rise  of  this  type  of  philosophy  we  may  see,  as  M.  Bergson 
himself  does,  the  revolt  ot  the  modern  man  of  action  against 
the  authority  of  Greece,  and  more  particularly  of  Plato  ;  or 
we  may  connect  it,  as  Dr.  Schiller  apparently  would  with 
imperialism  and  the  motor  car.  The  modern  world  calls 
for  such  a  philosophy,  and  the  success  which  it  has  achieved 
is  therefore  not  surprising. 

M.  Bergson's  philosophy,  unlike  most  of  the  systems  of 
the  past,  is  dualistic  :  the  woild,  for  him,  is  divided  into  two 
disparate  portions,  on  the  one  hand  life,  on  the  other  matter, 
or  rather  that  inert  something  which  the  intellect  views  as 
matter.  The  whole  universe  is  the  clash  and  conflict  of  two 
opposite  motions  :  life,  which  climbs  upward,  and  matter, 
which  falls  downward.  Life  is  one  great  force,  one  vast 
vital  impulse,  given  once  for  all  from  the  beginning  of  the 
world,  meeting  the  resistance  of  matter,  struggling  to  break 
a  way  through  matter,  learning  gradually  to  use  matter  by 
means  of  organisation  ;  divided  by  the  obstacles  it  encounters 
into  diverging  currents,  like  the  wind  at  the  street  corner  ; 
partly  subdued  by  matter  through  the  very  adaptations 
which  matter  forces  upon  it ;  yet  retaining  always  its  capacity 
for  free  activity,  struggling  always  to  find  new  outlets,  seeking 
always  for  greater  liberty  of  movement  amid  the  opposing 
walls  of,  matter. 

Evolution  is  not  primaiily  explicable  by  adaptation  to 
environment ;  adaptation  explains  only  the  turns  and  twists 
of  evolution,  like  the  windings  of  a  road  approaching  a  town 
through  hilly  country.     But  this  simile  is  not  quite  adequate  ; 


t 


there  is  no  town,  no  definite  goal,  at  the  end  of  the  road 
along  which  evolution  travels.  Mechanism  and  teleology 
suffer  from  the  same  defect  :  both  suppose  that  there  is  no 
essential  novelty  in  the  world.  Mechanism  regards  the  future 
as  implicit  in  the  past,  since  it  believes  the  future  to  be  cal- 
culable ;  teleology  also,  since  it  believes  that  the  end  to  be 
achieved  can  be  known  in  advance,  denies  that  any  essential 
novelty  is  contained  in  the  result. 

As  against  both  these  views,  though  with  more  sympathy 
for  teleology  than  for  mechanism,  J"  M.  Bergson  maintains 
that  evolution  is  truly  creative,  like  the  work  of  an  artist. 
An  impulse  to  action,  an  undefined  want,  exists  beforehand, 
but  until  the  want  is  satisfied  it  is  impossible  to  know  the 
nature  of  what  will  satisfy  it.  For  example,  we  may  suppose 
some  vague  desire  in  sightless  animals  to  be  able  to  be  aware 
of  objects  before  they  were  in  contact  with  them.  This  led 
to  efforts  which  finally  resulted  in  the  creation  of  eyes.  Sight 
satisfied  the  desire,  but  could  not  have  been  imagined  before- 
hand. For  this  reason,  evolution  is  unpredictable,  and 
determinism  cannot  refute  the  advocates  of  free  will. 

This  broad  outline  is  filled  in  by  an  account  of  the  actual 
development  oi  life  on  the  earth.  The  first  division  of  the 
current  was  into  plants  and  animals  :  plants  aimed  at  storing 
up  energy  in  a  reservoir,  animals  aimed  at  using  energy  for 
sudden  and  rapid  movements.  "The  same  impetus,"  he 
says,  "  that  has  led  the  animal  to  give  itself  nerves  and  nerve 
centres  must  have  ended,  in  the  plant,  in  the  chlorophyllian 
function"  (C.  E.,  p.  120).  But  among  animals,  at  a  later 
stage,  a  new  bifurcation  appeared  :  instinct  and  intellect 
became  more  or  less  separated.  They  are  never  wholly 
without  each  other,  but  in  the  main  intellect  is  the  misfortune 
of  man,  while  instinct  is  seen  at  its  best  in  ants,  bees,  and 
Bergson.  The  division  between  intellect  and  instinct  is 
fundamental  in  his  philosophy,  much  of  which  is  a  kind  of 
Sandford  and  Merton,  with  instinct  as  the  good  boy  and  in- 
tellect as  the  bad  boy. 

Instinct  at  its  best  is  called  intuition.     "  By  intuition," 


he  says,  "  I  mean  instinct  that  has  become  disinterested, 
self  conscious,  capable  of  reflecting  upon  its  object  and  of 
enlarging  it  indefinitely  "  (C.  E.,  p.  186).  The  account  of 
the  doings  of  intchect  is  not  always  easy  to  follow,  but  if 
we  are  to  understand  Bergson  we  murt  do  our  best. 

Intelligence  or  intellect,  "  as  it  leaves  the  hands  of 
nature,  has  for  its  chief  object  the  inorganic  solid  "  (C.  E., 
p.  162)  ;  it  can  only  form  a  clear  idea  of  the  discontinuous 
and  the  immobile  (pp.  163-4)  >  its  concepts  are  outside  each 
other  like  objects  in  space,  and  have  the  same  stability  (p. 
169).  The  intellect  separates  in  space  and  fixes  in  time  ; 
it  is  not  made  to  think  evolution,  but  represent  becoming 
as  a  series  of  states  (p.  171).  "  The  intellect  is  characterised 
by  a  natural  inability  to  understand  life  "  (p.  174)  ;  geometry 
and  logic,  which  are  its  typical  products,  are  strictly  applicable 
to  solid  bodies,  but  elsewhere  reasoning  must  be  checked  by 
common  sense,  which,  as  Bergson  truly  says,  is  a  very  different 
thing  (p.  170).  Solid  bodies,  it  would  seem,  are  something 
which  mind  has  created  on  purpose  to  apply  intellect  to  them, 
much  as  it  has  created  chess-boards  in  order  to  play  chess  on 
them.  The  genesis  of  intellect  and  the  genesis  of  material 
bodies,  we  are  told,  are  correlative  :  both  have  been  developed 
by  reciprocal  adaptation  (p.  196).  "  An  identical  process 
must  have  cut  out  matter  and  the  intellect,  at  the  same  time, 
from  a  stuff  that  contained  both  "  (p.  210). 

This  conception  of  the  simultaneous  growth  of  matter 
and  intellect  is  ingenious,  and  deserves  to  be  understood. 
Broadly,  I  think,  what  is  meant  is  this  :  Intellect  is  the  power 
of  seeing  thing?  as  separate  one  from  another,  and  matter  is 
that  which  is  separated  into  distinct  things  In  reality 
there  are  no  separate  solid  things,  only  an  end] ess  stream  of 
becoming,  in  which  nothing  becomes  and  there  is  nothing 
that  this  nothing  becomes.  But  becoming  may  be  a  move- 
ment up  or  a  movement  down  :  when  it  is  a  movement  up 
it  is  called  life,  when  it  is  a  movement  down  it  is  what,  as 
misapprehended  by  the  intellect,  is  called  matter.  I  suppose 
the  universe  is  shaped  like  a  cone,  with  the  Absolute  at  the 


vertex,  for  the  movement  up  brings  things  together,  while  the 
movement  down  separates  them,  or  at  least  seems  to  do  so. 
In  order  that  the  upward  motion  of  mind  may  be  able  to  thread 
its  way  through  the  downward  motion  of  the  falling  bodies 
which  hail  upon  it,  it  must  be  able  to  cut  out  paths  between 
them  ;  thus  as  intelligence  was  formed,  outlines  and  paths 
appeared  (p.  199),  and  the  primitive  flux  was  cut  up  into 
separate  bodies.  The  intellect  may  be  compared  to  a 
carver,  but  it  has  the  peculiarity  of  imagining  that  the  chicken 
was  always  the  separate  pieces  into  which  the  carving-knife 
divides  it. 

"  The  intellect,"  Bergson  says,  "  always  behaves  as  if 
it  were  fascinated  by  the  contemplation  of  inert  matter. 
It  is  life  looking  outward,  putting  itself  outside  itself,  adopting 
the  ways  of  inorganised  nature  in  principle,  in  order  to  direct 
them  in  fact  "  (p.  170).  If  we  may  be  allowed  to  add  another 
image  to  the  many  by  which  Bergson's  philosophy  is 
illustrated,  we  may  say  tnat  the  universe  is  a  vast  funicular 
railway,  in  which  life  is  the  train  that  goes  up,  and  matter  is 
the  train  that  goes  down.  The  intellect  consists  in  watching 
the  descending  train  as  it  passes  the  ascending  train  in  which 
we  are.  The  obviously  nobler  faculty  which  concentrates 
its  attention  on  our  own  train,  is  instinct  or  intuition.  It  is 
possible  to  leap  from  one  train  to  the  other  ;  this  happens 
when  we  become  the  victims  of  automatic  habit,  and  is  the 
essence  of  the  comic.  Or  we  can  divide  ourselves  into  parts, 
one  part  going  up  and  one  down ;  then  only  the  part 
going  down  is  comic.  But  intellect  is  not  itself  a  descending 
motion,  it  is  merely  an  observation  of  the  descending  motion 
by  the  ascending  motion. 

Intellect,  which  separates  things,  is,  according  to  Bergson, 
a  kind  of  dream ;  it  is  not  active,  as  all  our  life  ought  to  be, 
but  purely  contemplative.  When  we  dream,  he  says,  our 
self  is  scattered,  our  past  is  broken  into  fragments  (p.  212),* 


*  It  is  noteworthy  that  elsewhere  Bergson  speaks  of  dreams  as 
giving  us  duration  more  pure  than  in  waking  life  (T.  and  F.W.,  p.  126). 


thin^  which  really  interpenetrate  each  other  are  seen 
as  separate  solid  units  :  the  extra-spatial  degrades  itself  into 
spatiality  (p.  218),  which  is  nothing  hut  separateness.  Thus 
all  intellect,  since  it  separates,  tends  to  geometry,  and  logic, 
which  deals  with  concepts  that  lie  wholly  outside  each  other, 
is  really  an  outcome  of  geometry,  following  the  direction  of 
materiality  (pp.  222-4).  Both  deduction  and  induction 
require  spatial  intuition  behind  them  (p.  225)  ;  "  the  move- 
ment at  the  end  of  which  is  spatiality  lays  down  along  its  course 
the  faculty  of  induction,  as  well  as  that  of  deduction,  in  fact, 
intellectuality  entire."  It  creates  them  in  mind,  and  also 
the  order  in  things  which  the  intellect  finds  there  (p.  228). 
Thus  logic  and  mathematics  do  not  represent  a  positive 
spiritual  effort  (p.  224),  but  a  mere  somnambulism,  in  which 
the  will  is  suspended,  and  the  mind  is  no  longer  active.  In- 
capacity for  mathematics  is  therefore  a  sign  of  grace — 
fortunately  a  very  common  one. 

As  intellect  is  connected  with  space,  so  instinct  or  in- 
tuition is  connected  with  time.  It  is  one  of  the  noteworthy 
features  of  Bergson's  philosophy  that,  unlike  most  writers, 
he  regards  time  and  space  as  profoundly  dissimilar.  Space, 
the  characteristic  of  matter,  arises  from  a  dissection  of  the 
flux  which  is  really  illusory,  useful,  up  to  a  certain  point, 
in  practice,  but  utterly  misleading  in  theory.  Time,  on  the 
contrary,  is  the  essential  characteristic  of  life  or  mind. 
"  Wherever  anything  lives,"  he  says,  "  there  is,  open  some- 
where, a  register  in  which  time  is  being  inscribed"  (C.  E., 
p.  17).  But  the  time  here  spoken  of  is  not  mathematical 
time,  the  homogeneous  assemblage  of  mutually  external 
instants.  Mathematical  time,  according  to  Bergson,  is  really 
a  form  of  space  ;  the  time  which  is  of  the  essence  of  life  is 
what  he  calls  duration.  This  conception  of  duration  is  funda- 
mental in  his  philosophy  ;  it  appears  already  in  his  earliest 
book  Time  and  Free  Will,  and  it  is  necessary  to  understand 
it  if  we  are  to  have  any  comprehension  of  his  system.  It 
is,  however,  a  very  difficult  conception.     I  do  not  fully  under- 


stand  it  myself,  and  inerefore  I  cannot  hope  to  explain  it 
with  all  the  lucidity  which  it  doubtless  deserves. 

"  Pure  duration,"  we  are  told,  "  is  the  form  which  our 
conscious  states  assume  when  our  ego  lets  itself  live,  when 
it  refrains  from  separating  its  present  state  from  its  former 
states  "  (7\  and  F.  W.,  p.  ioo).  It  forms  the  past  and  the 
present  into  one  organic  whole,  where  there  is  mutual  penetra- 
tion, succession  without  distinction  (ib.).  "  Within  our  ego, 
there  is  succession  without  mutual  externality  ;  outside  the 
ego,  in  pure  space,  there  is  mutual  externality  without 
succession  "  (p.  108). 

"  Questions  relating  to  subject  and  object,  to  their 
distinction  and  their  union,  should  be  put  in  terms  of  time 
rather  than  of  space  "  (M.  and  M.,  p.  77).  In  the  duration 
in  which  we  see  ourselves  acting,  there  are  dissociated  elements  ; 
but  in  the  duration  in  which  we  act,  our  states  melt  into  each 
other  (M.  and  M.,  p.  243).  Pure  duration  is  what  is  most 
removed  from  externality  and  least  penetrated  with  exter- 
nality, a  duration  in  which  the  past  is  big  with  a  present 
absolutely  new.  But  then  our  will  is  strained  to  the  utmost  ; 
we  have  to  gather  up  the  past  which  is  slipping  away,  and 
thrust  it  whole  and  undivided  into  the  present.  At  such 
moments  we  truly  possess  ourselves,  but  such  moments  are 
rare  (C.  E.,  pp.  210-211).  Duration  is  the  very  stuff  of  reality, 
which  is  perpetual  becoming,  never  something  made  (C.  E., 
p.  287). 

It  is  above  all  in  memory  that  duration  exhibits  itself, 
for  in  memory  the  past  survives  in  the  present.  Thus  the 
theory  of  memory  becomes  of  great  importance  in  Bergson's 
philosophy.  Matter  and  Memory  is  concerned  to  show  the 
relation  of  mind  and  matter,  of  which  both  are  affirmed  to 
be  real  (p.  vii),  by  an  analysis  of  memory,  which  is  "  just 
the  intersection  of  mind  and  matter  "  (p.  xii). 

There  are,  to  begin  with,  two  radically  different  things, 
both  of  which  are  commonly  called  memory  ;  the  clear  dis- 
tinction between  these  two  is  one  of  the  best  things  in  Bergson. 
"  The  past  survives,"  he  says,  "  under  two  distinct  forms : 


8 

first,  in  motor  mechanisms  ;  secondly,  in  independent  recollec- 
tions "  (M.  and  M.,  p.  87).  For  example,  a  man  is  said  to 
remember  a  poem  if  he  can  repeat  it  by  heart,  that  is  to  say, 
if  he  has  acquired  a  certain  habit  or  mechanism  enabling  him 
to  repeat  a  former  action.  But  he  might,  at  least  theoretically, 
be  able  to  repeat  the  poem  without  any  recollection  of  the 
previous  occasions  on  which  he  has  read  it ;  thus  there  is  no 
consciousness  of  past  events  involved  in  this  sort  of  memory. 
The  second  sort,  which  alone  really  deserves  to  be  called 
memory,  is  exhibited  in  recollections  of  separate  occasions 
when  he  has  read  the  poem,  each  unique  and  with  a  date. 
Here  there  can  be  no  question  of  habit,  since  each  event  only 
occurred  once,  and  had  to  make  its  impression  immediately. 
It  is  suggested  that  in  some  way  everything  that  has  happened 
to  us  is  remembered,  but  as  a  rule,  only  what  is  useful  comes 
into  consciousness.  Apparent  failures  of  memory,  it  is  argued, 
are  not  really  failures  of  the  mental  part  of  memory,  but  of 
the  motor  mechanism  for  bringing  memory  into  action.  This 
view  is  supported  by  a  discussion  of  brain  physiology  and  the 
facts  of  amnesia,  from  which  it  is  held  to  result  that  true 
memory  is  not  a  function  of  the  brain  (M.  and  M.,  p.  315). 
The  past  must  be  acted  by  matter,  imagined  by  mind  (M.  and 
M.,  p.  298).  Memory  is  not  an  emanation  of  matter  ;  indeed 
the  contrary  would  be  nearer  the  truth  if  we  mean  matter  as 
grasped  in  concrete  perception,  which  always  occupies  a 
certain  duration  (M.  and  M.,  p.  237). 

"  Memory  must  be,  in  principle,  a  power  absolutely 
independent  of  matter.  If,  then,  spirit  is  a  reality,  it  is  here, 
in  the  phenomena  of  memory,  that  we  may  come  into  touch 
with  it  experimentally  "  (M.  and  M.,  p.  81). 

At  the  opposite  end  from  pure  memory  Bergson  places 
pure  perception,  in  regard  to  which  he  adopts  an  ultra-realist 
position.  "  In  pure  perception,"  he  says,  "  we  are  actually 
placed  outside  ourselves,  we  touch  the  reality  of  the  object 
in  an  immediate  intuition  "  (p.  84).  So  completely  does  he 
identify  perception  with  its  object  that  he  almost  refuses  to 
call  it  mental  at  all.     "  Pure  perception,"  he  says,  "  which 


is  the  lowest  degree  of  mind — mind  without  memory — is 
really  part  of  matter,  as  we  understand  matter  "  (M.  and  M., 
p.  297).  Pure  perception  is  constituted  by  dawning  action, 
its  actuality  lies  in  its  activity  (M.  and  M.,  p.  74).  It  is  in 
this  way  that  the  brain  becomes  relevant  to  perception,  for 
the  brain  is  not  an  instrument  of  representation,  but  an 
instrument  of  action  (M.  and  M.,  p.  83).  The  function  of  the 
brain  is  to  limit  our  mental  life  to  what  is  practically  useful. 
But  for  the  brain,  one  gathers,  everything  would  be  perceived, 
but  in  fact  we  only  perceive  what  interests  us  (cf.  M.  and  M., 
p.  34).  "  The  body,  always  turned  towards  action,  has  for 
its  essential  function  to  limit,  with  a  view  to  action,  the  life 
of  the  spirit  "  (M.  and  M.,  p.  233).  It  is,  in  fact,  an  in- 
strument of  choice. 

We  must  now  return  to  the  subject  of  instinct  or  intuition, 
as  opposed  to  intellect.  It  was  necessary  first  to  give  some 
account  of  duration  and  memory,  since  Bergson's  theories  of 
duration  and  memory  are  presupposed  in  his  account  of  in- 
tuition. In  man,  as  he  now  exists,  intuition  is  the  fringe 
or  penumbra  of  intellect  :  it  has  been  thrust  out  of  the  centre 
by  being  less  useful  in  action  than  intellect,  but  it  has  deeper 
uses  which  make  it  desirable. to  bring  it  back  into  greater 
prominence.  Bergson  wishes  to  make  intellect  "turn  in- 
wards on  itself,  and  awaken  the  potentialities  of  intuition 
which  still  slumber  within  it  "  (C.  E.,  p.  192).  The  relation 
between  instinct  and  intellect  is  compared  to  that  between 
sight  and  touch.  Intellect,  we  aie  told,  will  not  give  know- 
ledge of  things  at  a  distance  ;  indeed  the  function  of  science 
is  said  to  be  to  explain  all  peiceptions  in  terms  of  touch. 

"  Instinct  alone,"  he  says,  "  is  knowledge  at  a  distance. 
It  has  the  same  relation  to  intelligence  that  vision  has  to 
touch  "  (C.  E.,  p.  177).  We  may  observe  in  passing  that,  as 
appears  in  many  passages,  Bergson  is  a  strong  visualiser, 
whose  thought  is  always  conducted  by  means  of  visual  images. 
Many  things  which  he  declaies  to  be  necessities  of  all  thought 
are,  I  believe,  characteristic  of  visualisers,  and  would  not  be 
true  of  those  who  think  by  means  of  auditory  images.     He 


10 


always  exalts  the  sense  of  sight  at  the  expense  of  the  other 
senses,  and  his  views  on  space  would  seem  to  be  largely 
determined  by  this  fact.  I  shall  return  to  this  question  at  a 
later  stage. 

The  essential  characteristic  of  intuition  is  that  it  does 
not  divide  the  world  into  separate  things,  as  the  intellect 
does  ;  although  Bergson  does  not  use  these  words,  we  might 
describe  it  as  synthetic  rather  than  analytic.  It  apprehends 
a  multiplicity,  but  a  multiplicity  of  interpenetrating  processes, 
not  of  spatially  external  bodies.  There  are  in  truth  no  things  : 
I "  things  and  states  are  only  views,  taken  by  our  mind,  of 
becoming.  There  are  no  things,  there  are  only  actions  " 
(C.  E.,  p.  261).  This  view  of  the  world,  which  appears 
difficult  and  unnatural  to  intellect,  is  easy  and  natural  to 
intuition.  Memory  affords  an  instance  of  what  is  meant,  for 
in  memory  the  past  lives  on  into  the  present  and  intei  pene- 
trates it.  Apart  from  mind* 'The  world  would*  be  perpetually 
dying  and  being  born  again  ;  the  past  would  have  no  reality, 
and  therefore  there  would  be  no  past.  It  is  memory,  with  its 
correlative  desire,  that  makes'the  past  and  the  future  real 
and  therefore  creates  tiue  duration)and  true  time.  Intuition 
alone  can  understand  this  mingling  of  past  and  future  :  to 
the  intellect  they  remain  external,  spatially  external  as  it  were, 
to  one  another.  Under  the  guidance  of  intuition,  we  perceive 
that  "  form  is  only  a  snapshot  view  of  a  transition  "  (C.  E., 
p.  319),  and  the  philosopher  "  will  see  the  material  world 
melt  back  into  a  single  flux  "  (C.  E.,  p.  390). 

Closely  connected  with  the  merits  of  intuition  is  Bergson's 
doctrine  of  freedom  and  his  praise  of  action.  "  In  reality," 
he  says,  "  a  living  being  is  a  centre  of  action.  It  represents 
a  certain  sum  of  contingency  entering  into  the  world,  that  is 
to  say,  a  certain  quantity  of  possible  action  "  (C.  E.,  p.  276). 
The  arguments  against  free  will  depend  partly  upon  assuming 
that  the  intensity  of  psychical  states  is  a  quantity,  capable,  at 
least  in  theory,  of  numerical  measurement  ;  this  view  Bergson 
undertakes  to  refute  in  the  first  chapter  of  Time  and  Free  Will. 
Partly  the  determinist  depends,  we  are  told,  upon  a  confusion 


II 


between  true  duration  and  mathematical  time,  which  Bergson 
regards  as  really  a  form  of  space.  Partly,  again,  the  deter - 
minist  rests  his  case  upon  the  unwarranted  assumption  that, 
when  the  state  of  the  brain  is  given,  the  state  of  the  mind  is 
theroretically  determinate.  Bergson  is  willing  to  admit  that 
the  converse  is  true  that  is  to  say,  that  the  state  of  brain  is 
determinate  when  the  state  of  mind  is  given,  but  he  regards 
the  mind  as  more  differentiated  than  the  brain,  and  therefore 
holds  that  many  different  states  of  mind  may  correspond  to 
one  state  of  brain.  He  concludes  that  rea1  freedom  is  possible  : 
"  We  are  free  when  our  acts  spring  from  our  whole  personality, 
when  they  express  it,  when  they  have  that  indefinable  resem- 
blance to  it  whicn  one  sometimes  finds  between  the  artist  and 
his  work  "  [T.  and  F.  W.,  p.  172). 

In  the  above  outline,  I  have  in  the  main  endeavoured 
merely  to  state  Bergson's  views,  without  giving  the  reasons 
adduced  by  him  in  favour  of  their  truth.  This  is  easier  than 
it  would  be  with  most  philosophers,  since  as  a  rule  he  does 
not  give  reasons  for  his  opinions,  but  relies  on  their  inherent 
attractiveness,  and  on  the  charm  of  an  excellent  style.  Like 
the  advertisers  of  Oxo,  he  relies  upon  picturesque  and  varied 
statement,  and  an  apparent  explanation  of  many  obscure 
facts.  Analogies  and  similes,  especially  form  a  very  laige 
part  of  the  whole  process  by  which  he  recommends  his  views 
to  the  reader.  The  number  of  similes  for  life  to  be  found  in 
his  works  exceeds  the  number  in  any  poet  known  to  me. 
Life,  he  says,  is  like  a  shell  bursting  into  fragments  which  are 
again  shells  (C.  £.,  p.  103).  It  is  like  a  sheaf  (ib.,  p.  104). 
Initially,  it  was  "  a  tendency  to  accumulate  in  a  reservoir, 
as  do  especially  the  green  parts  of  vegetables  "  (ib.,  p.  260). 
But  the  reservoir  is  to  be  filled  with  boUing  water  from  which 
steam  is  issuing  ;  "jets  must  be  gushing  out  unceasingly.,  of 
which  each,  falling  back,  is  a  woild  "  (ib.,  p.  261).  Again, 
"  life  appears  in  its  entirety  as  an  immense  wave  which, 
starting  from  a  centre,  spreads  outwards,  and  which  on  almost 
the  whole  of  its  circumf ei  ence  is  stopped  and  converted  into 
oscillation  :  at  one  single  point  the  obstacle  has  been  forced, 


12 


the  impulsion  has  passed  freely  "  (ib.,  p.  280).  Then  there  is 
the  great  climax  in  which  life  is  compaied  to  a  cavalry  charge. 
"  All  organised  beings,  fiom  the  humblest  to  the  highest, 
from  the  first  origins  of  life  to  the  time  in  which  we  are,  and 
in  all  places  as  in  aU  times,  do  but  evidence  a  single  impulsion, 
the  inverse  of  the  movement  of  matter,  and  in  itself  indivisible. 
All  the  living  hold  together,  and  all  yield  to  the  same 
tremendous  push.  The  animal  takes  its  stand  on  the  plant, 
man  best  rides  animality,  and  the  whole  of  humanity,  in  space 
and  in  time,  is  one  immense  army  galloping  beside  and  before 
and  behind  each  of  us  in  an  overwhelming  charge  able  to  beat 
down  every  resistance  and  to  clear  many  obstacles,  perhaps 
even  death  "  (C.  E.,  pp.  285-6). 

But  a  cool  critic,  who  feels  himself  a  mere  spectator, 
perhaps  an  unsympathetic  spectator,  of  the  charge  in  which 
man  is  mounted  upon  animality,  m?y  be  inclined  to  think 
that  calm  and  careful  thought  is  haidly  compatible  with 
this  form  of  exercise.  When  he  is  told  that  thought  is  a 
mere  means  of  action,  the  mere  impulse  to  avoid  obstacles 
in  the  field,  he  may  feel  that  such  a  view  is  becoming  in  a 
cavalry  officer,  but  not  in  a  philosopher,  whose  business,  after 
all,  is  wi+h  thought  :  he  may  feel  that  in  the  passion  and  noise 
of  violent  motion  there  is  no  room  for  the  fainter  music  of 
reason,  no  leisure  for  the  disinterested  contemplation  in  which 
greatness  is  sought,  not  by  turbulence,  but  by  the  greatness 
of  the  universe  wlrch  is  mirrored.  In  that  case,  he  may  be 
tempted  to  ask  whether  there  are  any  reasons  for  accepting 
such  a  restless  view  of  the  world.  And  if  he  asks  this  question, 
he  will  find,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  that  there  is  no  reason 
whatever  for  accepting  this  view,  either  in  the  universe  or  in 
the  writings  of  M.  Bergson. 

11. 

The  two  foundations  of  Bergson's  philosophy,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  more  than  an  imaginative  and  poetic  view  of  the 
world,  are  his  doctrines  of  space  and  time.  His  doctrine  of 
space  is  required  for  his  condemnation  of  the  intellect,  and 


13 

if  he  fails  in  his  condemnation  of  the  intellect,  the  intellect 
will  succeed  in  its  condemnation  of  him,  for  between  the  two 
it  is  war  to  the  knife.  His  doctrine  of  time  is  necessary  for 
his  vindication  of  freedom,  for  his  escape  from  what  William 
James  called  a  "  block  universe,"  foi  his  doctrine  of  a  perpetual 
flux  in  which  there  is  nothing  that  flows,  and  for  his  whole 
account  of  the  relations  between  mind  and  matter.  It  will 
be  well,  therefore,  in  criticism,  to  concentrate  on  these  two 
doctrines.  If  they  are  true,  such  minor  errors  and  incon- 
sistencies as  no  philosopher  escapes  would  not  greatly  matter, 
while  if  they  are  false,  nothing  remains  except  an  imaginative 
epic,  to  be  judged  on  esthetic  rather  than  on  intellectual 
grounds.  I  shall  begin  with  the  theory  of  space,  as  being  the 
simpler  of  the  two. 

Bergson's  theory  of  space  occurs  fully  and  explicitly 
in  his  Time  and  Free  Will,  and  therefore  belongs  to  the  oldest 
parts  of  his  philosophy.  In  his  first  chapter,  he  contends 
that  greater  and  less  imply  space,  since  he  regards  the  great  et- 
as essentially  that  which  contains  the  less.  He  offers  no 
arguments  whatever,  either  good  or  bad,  in  favour  of  this  view  ; 
he  merely  exclaims,  as  though  he  were  giving  an  obvious 
reductio  ad  absurdum  :  "  As  if  one  could  still  speak  of  magni- 
tude where  there  is  neither  multiplicity  nor  space  I"  (p.  9). 
The  obvious  cases  to  the  contrary,  such  as  pleasure  and  pain, 
afford  him  much  difficulty,  yet  he  never  doubts  or  re-examines 
the  dogma  with  which  he  starts. 

In  his  next  chapter,  he  maintains  the  same  thesis  as 
regards  number.  "  As  soon  as  we  wish  to  picture  number 
to  ourselves,"  he  says,  "  and  not  merely  figures  or  words, 
we  are  compelled  to  have  recourse  to  an  extended  image  " 
(p.  78),  and  "  every  clear  idea  of  number  implies  a  visual 
image  in  space  "  (p.  79).  These  two  sentences  suffice  to  show, 
as  I  shall  try  to  prove,  that  Bergson  does  not  know  what 
number  is,  and  has  himself  no  clear  idea  of  it.  This  is  shown 
also  by  his  definition  :  "  Number  may  be  defined  in  general 
as  a  collection  of  units,  or,  speaking  more  exactly,  as  the 
synthesis  of  the  one  and  the  many  "  (p.  75). 


14 

In  discussing  these  statements,  I  must  ask  the  reader's 
patience  for  a  moment  while  I  call  attention  to  some  distinc- 
tions which  may  at  first  appear  pedantic,  but  are  really  vital. 
There  are  three  entirely  different  things  which  are  confused 
by  Bergson  in  the  above  statements,  namely  :  (i)  number, 
the  general  concept  applicable  to  the  various  particular 
numbers  ;  (2)  the  various  particular  numbers  ;  (3)  the  various 
collections  to  which  the  various  particular  numbers  are 
applicable.  It  is  this  last  that  is  defined  by  Bergson  when 
he  says  that  number  is  a  collection  of  units.  The  twelve 
apostles,  the  twelve  tribes  of  Israel,  the  twelve  months,  the 
twelve  signs  of  the  zodiac,  are  all  collections  of  units,  yet  no 
one  of  them  is  the  number  12,  still  less  is  it  number  in  general, 
as  by  the  above  definition  it  ought  to  be.  The  number  12, 
obviously,  is  something  which  all  these  collections  have  in 
common  but  which  they  do  not  have  in  common  with  other 
collections,  such  as  cricket  elevens.  Hence  the  number 
12  is  neither  a  collection  of  twelve  terms,  nor  is  it  some- 
thing which  all  collections  have  in  common  ;  and  number 
in  general  is  a  property  of  12  or  11  or  any  other  number, 
but  not  of  the  various  collections  that  have  twelve  terms  or 
eleven  terms. 

Hence  when,  following  Bergson's  advice,  we  "  have 
recourse  to  an  extended  image  "  and  picture,  say,  twelve  dots 
such  as  are  obtained  by  throwing  double  sixes  at  dice,  we 
have  still  not  obtained  a  picture  of  the  number  12.  The 
number  12,  in  fact,  is  something  more  abstract  than  any 
picture.  Before  we  can  be  said  to  have  any  understanding 
of  the  number  12,  we  must  know  what  different  collections 
of  twelve  units  have  in  common,  and  this  is  something  which 
cannot  be  pictured  because  it  is  abstract.  Bergson  only 
succeeds  in  making  his  theory  of  number  plausible  by  confusing 
a  particular  collection  with  the  number  of  its  terms,  and  this 
again  with  number  in  general. 

The  confusion  is  the  same  as  if  we  confused  a  particular 
young  man  with  youth,  and  youth  with  the  general  concept 
"  period  of  human  life,"  and  were  then  to  argue  that  because 


15 

a  young  man  has  two  legs,  youth  must  have  two  legs,  and 
the  general  concept  "  period  of  human  life  "  must  have  two 
legs.  The  confusion  is  important  because,  as  soon  as  it  is 
perceived,  the  theory  that  number  or  particular  numbers 
can  be  pictured  in  space  is  seen  to  be  untenable.  This  not 
only  disproves  Bergson's  theory  as  to  number,  but  also  his 
more  general  theory  that  all  abstract  ideas  and  all  logic 
are  derived  from  space  ;  for  the  abstract  12,  the  common 
property  of  all  dozens  as  opposed  to  any  particular  dozen, 
though  it  is  never  present  to  his  mind,  is  obviously  conceivable 
and  obviously  incapable  of  being  pictured  in  space. 

But  apart  from  the  question  of  numbers,  shall  we  admit 
Bergson's  contention  that  every  plurality  of  separate  units 
involves  space  ?  Some  of  the  cases  that  appear  to  contradict 
this  view  are  coi  sidered  by  him,  for  example  successive 
sounds.  When  we  hear  the  steps  of  a  passer-by  in  the  street, 
he  says,  we  visualise  his  successive  positions  ;  when  we  hear 
the  strokes  of  a  bell,  we  either  picture  it  swinging  backwards 
and  forwards,  or  we  range  the  successive  sounds  in  an  ideal 
space  (T.  and  F.  W.,  p.  86).  But  these  are  mere  autobio- 
graphical observations  of  a  visualiser,  and  illustrate  the 
remark  we  made  before,  that  Bergson's  views  depend  upon  the 
predominance  of  the  sense  of  sight  in  him.  There  is  no  logical 
necessity  to  range  the  strokes  of  a  clock  in  an  imaginary 
space  :  most  people,  I  imagine,  count  them  without  any 
spatial  auxiliary.  Yet  no  reason  is  alleged  by  Bergson  for 
the  view  that  space  is  necessary.  He  assumes  this  as  obvious, 
and  proceeds  at  once  to  apply  it  to  the  case  of  times.  Where 
there  seem  to  be  different  times  outside  each  other,  he  says, 
the  times  aie  pictured  as  spread  out  in  space ;  in  real  time, 
such  as  is  given  by  memory,  different  times  interpenetrate 
each  other,  and  cannot  be  counted  because  they  are  not 
separate. 

The  view  that  all  separateness  implies  space  is  now 
supposed  estabhshed,  and  is  used  deductively  to  prove  that 
space  is  involved  wherever  there  is  obviously  separateness , 
however  little  other  reason  there  may  be  for  suspecting  such 


i6 


a  thing.  Thus  abstract  ideas  foi  example,  obviously  exclude 
each  other  :  whiteness  is  differenc  from  blackness,  health  is 
different  from  sickness,  folly  is  different  from  wisdom.  Hence 
all  abstract  ideas  involve  space  ;  and  therefore  logic,  which 
uses  abstract  ideas,  is  an  offshot  of  geometry,  and  the  whole 
of  the  intellect  depends  upon  a  supposed  habit  of  picturing 
things  side  by  side  in  space.  This  conclusion,  upon  which 
Bergson's  whole  condemnation  of  the  intellect  rests,  is  based, 
so  far  as  can  be  discovered,  entirely  upon  a  personal  idio- 
syncrasy mistaken  for  a  necessity  of  thought,  I  mean  the 
idiosyncrasy  of  visualising  successions  as  spread  out  on  a  line. 
The  instance  of  numbers  shows  that,  if  Bergson  were  in  the 
right,  we  could  never  have  attained  to  the  abstract  ideas 
which  are  supposed  to  be  thus  impregnated  with  space  ; 
and  conversely,  the  fact  that  we  can  understand  abstract 
ideas  (as  opposed  to  particular  things  which  exemplify  them) 
seems  sufficient  to  prove  that  he  is  wrong  in  regarding  the 
intellect  as  impregnated  with  space. 

One  of  the  bad  effects  of  an  anti-intellectual  philosophy, 
such  as  that  of  Bergson,  it  that  it  thrives  upon  the  errors 
and  confusions  of  the  intellect.  Hence  it  is  led  to  prefer  bad 
thinking  to  good,  to  declare  every  momentary  difficulty 
insoluble,  and  to  regard  every  foolish  mistake  as  revealing 
the  bankruptcy  of  intellect  and  the  triumph  of  intuition. 
There  are  in  Bergson's  works  many  allusions  to  mathematics 
and  science,  and  to  a  careless  reader  these  allusions  may  seem 
to  strengthen  his  philosophy  greatly.  As  regards  science, 
especially  biology  and  physiology,  I  am  not  competent  to 
criticise  his  interpretations.  But  as  regards  mathematics, 
he  has  deliberately  preferred  traditional  errors  in  interpretation 
to  the  more  modern  -views  which  have  prevailed  among 
mathematicians  for  the  last  half  century.  In  this  matter,  he 
has  followed  the  example  of  most  philosophers.  In  the 
eighteenth  and  early  nineteenth  centuries,  the  infinitesimal 
calculus,  though  well  developed  as  a  method,  was  supported, 
as  regards  its  foundations,  by  many  fallacies  and  much  con- 
fused thinking.     Hegel  and  his  followers  seized  upon  these 


17 

fallacies  and  confusion?,  to  support  them  in  their  attempt 
to  prove  all  mathematics  self-contradictory.  Thence  the 
Hegelian  account  of  these  matters  passed  into  the  current 
thought  of  philosophers,  where  it  has  remained  long  after 
the  mathematicians  have  removed  all  the  difficulties  upon 
which  the  philosophers  rely.  And  so  long  as  the  main  object 
of  philosophers  is  to  show  that  nothing  can  be  learned  by 
patience  and  detailed  thinking,  but  that  we  ought  rather  to 
worship  the  prejudices  of  the  ignorant  under  the  title  of 
"  reason  "  if  we  are  Hegelians,  or  of  "  intuition  "  if  we  are 
Bergsonians,  so  long  philosophers  will  take  care  to  remain 
ignorant  of  what  mathematicians  have  done  to  remove  the 
errors  by  which  Hegel  profited. 

Apart  from  the  question  of  number  which  we  have 
already  considered,  the  chief  point  at  which  Bergson  touches 
mathematics  is  his  rejection  of  what  he  calls  the  "  cinemato- 
graphic "  representation  of  the  world.  Mathematics  con- 
ceives change,  even  continuous  change,  as  constituted  by  a 
series  of  states  ;  Bergson,  on  the  contrary,  contends  that  no 
series  of  states  can  represent  what  is  continuous,  and  that 
in  change  a  thing  is  never  in  any  state  at  all.  This  view 
that  change  is  constituted  by  a  series  of  changing  states  he 
calls  cinematographic  ;  this  view,  he  says,  is  natural  to  the 
intellect,  but  is  radically  vicious.  True  change  can  only  be 
explained  by  true  duration  ;  it  involves  an  interpenetration 
of  past  and  present,  not  a  mathematical  succession  of  static 
states.  This  is  what  is  called  a  "  dynamic  "  instead  of  a 
"  static  "  view  of  the  world.  The  question  is  important,  and 
in  spite  of  its  difficulty  we  cannot  pass  it  by. 

Bergson's  position  is  illustrated — and  what  is  to  be  said 
in  criticism  may  also  be  aptly  illustrated — by  Zeno's  argument 
of  the  arrow.  Zeno  argues  that,  since  the  arrow  at  each 
moment  simply  is  where  it  is,  thereforethe  arrow  in  its  flight 
is  always  at  rest.  At  first  sight,  this  argument  may  not  appear 
a  very  powerful  one.  Of  course,  it  will  be  said,  the  arrow 
is  where  it  is  at  one  moment,  but  at  another  moment  it  is 
somewhere  else,   and  this  is  just  was  constitutes   motion. 


i8 

Certain  difficulties,  it  is  true,  arise  out  of  the  continuity  of 
motion,  if  we  insist  upon  assuming  that  motion  is  also  dis- 
continuous. These  difficulties,  thus  obtained,  have  long  been 
part  of  the  stock-in-trade  of  philosophers.  But  if,  with  the 
mathematicians,  we  avoid  the  assumption  that  motion  is  also 
discontinuous,  we  shall  not  fall  into  the  philosopher's 
difficulties.  A  cinematograph  in  which  there  are  an  infinite 
number  of  films,  and  in  which  there  is  never  a  next  film  because 
an  infinite  number  come  between  any  two,  will  perfectly 
represent  a  continuous  motion.  Wherein,  then,  lies  the  force 
of  Zeno's  argument  ? 

Zeno  belonged  to  the  Eleatic  school,  whose  object  was 
to  prove  that  there  could  be  no  such  thing  as  change.  The 
natural  view  to  take  of  the  world  is  that  there  are  things 
which  change  ;  for  example,  there  is  an  arrow  which  is  now 
here,  now  there.  By  bisection  of  this  view,  philosophers 
have  developed  two  paradoxes.  The  Eleatics  said  that 
there  were  things  but  no  changes  ;  Heraclitus  and  Bergson 
said  that  there  were  changes  but  no  things.  The  Eleatics 
said  there  was  an  arrow,  but  no  flight  ;  Heraclitus  and  Bergson 
said  there  was  a  flight  but  no  arrow.  Each  party  conducted 
its  argument  by  refutation  of  the  other  party.  How  ridiculous 
to  say  there  is  no  arrow  !  say  the  "  static  "  party.  How 
ridiculous  to  say  there  is  no  flight !  say  the  "  dynamic  " 
party.  The  unfortunate  man  who  stands  in  the  middle 
and  maintains  that  there  is  both  the  arrow  and  its  flight  is 
assumed  by  the  disputants  to  deny  both  ;  he  is  therefore 
pierced,  like  St.  Sebastian,  by  the  arrow  from  one  side  and  by 
its  flight  from  the  other.  But  we  have  still  not  discovered 
wherein  lies  the  force  of  Zeno's  argument. 

Zeno  assumes,  tacitly,  the  essence  of  the  Bergsonian 
theory  of  change.  That  is  to  say,  he  assumes  that  when  a 
thing  is  in  a  process  of  continuous  change,  even  if  it  is  only 
change  of  position,  there  must  be  in  the  thing  some  internal 
state  of  change.  The  thing  must,  at  each  instant,  be  in- 
trinsically different  from  what  it  would  be  if  it  were  not 
changing.     He  then  points  out  that  at  each  instant  the  arrow 


*9 

simply  is  where  it  is,  just  as  it  would  be  if  it  were  at  rest. 
Hence  he  concludes  that  there  can  be  no  such  thing  as  a  state 
of  motion,  and  therefore,  adhering  to  the  view  that  a  state  of 
motion  is  essential  to  motion,  he  infers  that  there  can  be  no 
motion  and  that  the  arrow  is  always  at  rest. 

Zeno's  argument,  therefore,  though  it  does  not  touch 
the  mathematical  account  of  change,  does,  prima  facie, 
refute  a  view  of  change  which  is  not  unlike  M.  Bergson's. 
How,  then,  does  M.  Bergson  meet  Zeno's  argument  ?  He 
meets  it  by  denying  that  the  arrow  is  ever  anywhere.  After 
stating  Zeno's  argument,  he  replies  :  "  Yes,  if  we  suppose 
that  the  arrow  can  ever  be  in  a  point  of  its  course.  Yes 
again,  if  the  arrow,  which  is  moving,  ever  coincides  with  a 
position,  which  is  motionless.  But  the  arrow  never  is  in 
any  point  of  its  course  "  (C.  E.,  p.  325).  This  reply  to  Zeno, 
or  a  closely  similar  one  concerning  Achilles  and  the  Tortoise, 
occurs  in  all  his  three  books.  Bergson's  view,  plainly,  is 
paradoxical ;  whether  it  is  possible,  is  a  question  which 
demands  a  discussion  of  his  view  of  duration.  His  only  argu- 
ment in  its  favour  is  the  statement  that  the  mathematical 
view  of  change  "  implies  the  absurd  proposition  that  move- 
ment is  made  of  immobilitie^  "  (C.  E.,  p.  325).  But  the 
apparent  absurdity  of  this  view  is  merely  due  to  the  verbal 
form  in  which  he  has  stated  it,  and  vanishes  as  soon  as  we 
realise  that  motion  implies  relations.  A  friendship,  for 
example,  is  made  out  of  people  who  are  friends,  but  not  out  of 
friendships  ;  a  genealogy  is  made  out  of  men,  but  not  out  of 
genealogies.  So  a  motion  is  made  out  of  what  is  moving, 
but  not  out  of  motions.  It  expresses  the  fact  that  a  thing 
ma}'  be  in  different  places  at  different  times,  and  that  the  places 
may  still  be  different,  however  near  together  the  times  may 
be.  Bergson's  argument  against  the  mathematical  view  of 
motion,  therefore,  reduces  itself,  in  the  last  analysis,  to  a  mere 
play  upon  words.  And  with  this  conclusion  we  may  pass 
on  to  a  criticism  of  his  theory  of  duration. 

Bergson's  theory  of  duration  is  bound  up  with  his  theory 
of  memory.     According  to  this  theory,  things  remembered 


20 


survive  in  memory,  and  thus  interpenetrate  present  things  : 
past  and  present  are  not  mutually  external,  but  are  mingled 
in  the  unity  of  consciousness.  Action,  he  says,  is  what 
constitutes  being  ;  but  mathematical  time  is  a  mere  passive 
receptacle,  which  does  nothing  and  therefore  is  nothing 
(C.  £".,  p.  41).  The  past,  he  says,  is  that  which  acts  no  longer, 
and  the  present  is  that  which  is  acting  (M.  and  M.,  p.  74). 
But  in  this  statement,  as  indeed  throughout  his  account  of 
duration,  Bergson  is  unconsciously  assuming  the  ordinary 
mathematical  time  ;  without  this,  his  statements  are  unmean- 
ing. What  is  meant  by  saying  "  the  past  is  essentially  that 
which  acts  no  longer  "  (his  italics),  except  that  the  past  is  that 
of  which  the  action  is  past  ?  The  words  "  no  longer  "  are 
words  expressive  of  the  past ;  to  a  person  who  did  not  have 
the  ordinary  notion  of  the  past  as  something  outside  the 
present,  these  words  would  have  no  meaning.  Thus  his 
definition  is  circular.  What  he  says  is,  in  effect,  "  the  past 
is  that  of  which  the  action  is  in  the  past."  As  a  definition, 
this  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  happy  effort.  And  the  same 
applies  to  the  present.  The  present,  we  are  told,  is  "  thai 
which  is  acting  "  (his  italics).*  But  the  word  "  is  "  introduces 
just  that  idea  of  the  present  which  was  to  be  defined.  The 
present  is  that  which  is  acting  as  opposed  to  that  which  was 
acting  or  will  be  acting.  That  is  to  say,  the  present  is  that 
whose  action  is  in  the  present,  not  in  the  past  or  in  the  future. 
Again  the  definition  is  circular.  An  earlier  passage  on  the 
same  page  will  illustrate  the  fallacy  further.  "  That  which 
constitutes  our  pure  perception,"  he  says,  "  is  our  dawning 
action.  .  .  .  The  actuality  of  our  perception  thus  lies  in 
its  activity,  in  the  movements  which  prolong  it,  and  not  in 
its  greater  intensity  :  the  past  is  only  idea,  the  present  is 
ideo-motor  "  (ib.).  This  passage  makes  it  quite  clear  that, 
when  Bergson  speaks  of  the  past,  he  does  not  mean  the  past, 


*  Similarly  in  Matter  and  Memory  (p.  193)  he  says  it  is  a  question 
whether  the  past  has  ceased  to  exist,  or  has  only  ceased  to  be  useful. 
The  present,  he  says,  is  not  that  which  is,  but  that  which  is  being  made. 
The  words  1  have  italicized  here  really  involve  the  usual  view  of  time. 


21 


but  our  present  memory  of  the  past.  The  past  when  it  existed 
was  just  as  active  as  the  present  is  now  ;  if  Bergson's  account 
were  correct,  the  present  moment  ought  to  be  the  only  one 
in  the  whole  history  of  the  world  containing  any  activity. 

In  earlier  times  there  were  other  perceptions,  just  as 
active,  just  as  actual  in  their  day,  as  our  present  perception  ; 
the  past,  in  its  day,  was  by  no  means  only  idea,  but  was  in  its 
intrinsic  character  just  what  the  present  is  now.  This  real 
past,  however,  Bergson  simply  forgets  ;  what  he  speaks  of 
is  the  present  idea  of  the  past.  The  real  past  does  not  mingle 
with  the  present.  Our  memory  of  the  past  does  of  course 
mingle  with  the  present,  since  it  is  part  of  it  ;  but  that  is  a 
very  different  thing. 

The  whole  of  Bergson's  theory  of  duration  and  time 
rests  throughout  on  the  elementary  confusion  between  the 
present  occurrence  of  a  recollection  and  the  past  occurrence 
whicn  is  recollected.  But  for  the  fact  that  time  is  so  familiar 
to  us,  the  vicious  circle  involved  in  his  attempt  to  deduce 
the  past  as  what  is  no  longer  active  would  be  obvious  at 
once.  As  it  is,  what  Bergson  gives  is  an  account  of  the 
difference  between  perception  and  recollection — both  present 
facts — and  what  he  believes  himself  to  have  given  is  an 
account  of  the  difference  between  the  present  and  the  past. 
As  soon  as  this  confusion  is  realised,  his  theory  of  time  is 
seen  to  be  simply  a  theory  which  omits  time  altogether. 

The  confusion  between  present  remembering  and  the 
past  event  remembered,  which  seems  to  be  at  the  bottom 
of  Bergson's  theory  of  time,  is  an  instance  of  a  more  general 
confusion  which,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  vitiates  a  great  deal 
of  his  thought,  and  indeed  a  great  deal  of  the  thought  of  most 
modern  philosophers — I  mean  the  confusion  between  an  act 
of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known.  In  memory,  the  act  of 
knowing  is  in  the  present,  whereas  what  is  known  is  in  the 
past ;  thus  by  confusing  them  the  distinction  between  past 
and  present  is  blurred.  In  perception,  the  act  of  knowing  is 
mental,  whereas  what  is  known  is  (at  least  in  one  sense) 
physical  or  material ;  thus  by  confusing  the  two,  the  distinction 


22 

between  mind  and  matter  is  blurred.  This  enables  Bergson 
to  say,  as  we  saw,  that  "  pure  perception,  which  is  the  lowest 
degree  of  mind  ...  is  really  part  of  matter."  The  act  of 
perceiving  is  mind,  while  that  which  is  perceived  is  (in  one 
sense)  matter  ;  thus  when  these  two  are  confused,  the  above 
statement  becomes  intelligible. 

Throughout  Matter  and  Memory,  this  confusion  between 
the  act  of  knowing  and  the  object  known  is  indispensable. 
It  is  enshrined  in  the  use  of  the  word  "  image,"  which  is 
explained  at  the  very  beginning  of  the  book.*  He  there  states 
that,  apart  from  philosophical  theories,  everything  that  we 
know  consists  of  "  images,"  which  indeed  constitute  the  whole 
universe.  He  says  :  "  I  call  matter  the  aggregate  of  images, 
and  perception  of  matter  these  same  images  referred  to  the 
eventual  action  of  one  particular  image,  my  body  "  (M.  and  M., 
p.  8).  It  will  be  observed  that  matter  and  the  perception  of 
matter,  according  to  him,  consist  of  the  very  same  things. 
The  brain,  he  says,  is  like  the  rest  of  the  material  universe, 
and  is  therefore  an  image  if  the  universe  is  an  image  (p.  9). 

Since  the  brain,  which  nobody  sees,  is  not,  in  the  ordinary 
sense,  an  image,  we  are  not  surprised  at  his  saying  that  an 
image  can  be  without  being  perceived  (p.  27)  ;  but  he  explains 
later  on  thai;,  as  regards  images,  the  difference  between  being 
and  being  consciously  perceived  is  only  one  of  degree  (p.  30). 
This  is  perhaps  explained  by  another  passage  in  which  he 
says  :  "  What  can  be  a  non-perceived  material  object,  an 
image  not  imaged,  unless  it  is  a  kind  of  unconscious  mental 
state  ?  "  (p.  183).  Finally  (p.  304)  he  says  :  "  That  every 
reality  lias  a  kinship,  an  analogy,  in  short  a  relation  with 
consciousness — this  is  what  we  concede  to  idealism  by  the 
very  fact  that  we  term  things  '  images.'  "  Nevertheless  he 
attempts  to  allay  our  initial  doubt  by  saying  that  he  is  begin- 


*  Bergson's  use  of  the  word  "  image  "  is  made  clearer  by  a  very 
penetrating  analysis  of  Berkeley  in  a  recent  article,  "  L'lntuition 
Philosophique "  (Revue  de  Mrtaphysique  et  de  Morale,  Nov.  191 1). 
This  article  displays  very  distinctly  the  profound  influence  of  Berkeley 
on  Bergson's  thought.  Bergson's  "image"  is  practically  Berkeley's 
"  idea." 


23 

ning  at  a  point  before  any  of  the  assumptions  of  philosophers 
have  been  introduced.  "  We  will  assume,"  he  says,  "  for 
the  moment  that  we  know  nothing  of  theories  of  matter  and 
theories  of  spirit,  nothing  of  the  discussions  as  to  the  reahty 
or  ideaUty  of  the  external  world.  Here  I  am  in  the  presence 
of  images  "  (p.  i).  And  in  the  new  Introduction  which  he 
wrote  for  the  English  edition  he  says  :  "  By  '  image  '  we  mean 
a.  certain  existence  which  is  more  than  that  which  the  ideaHst 
calls  a  representation,  but  less  than  that  which  tne  realist  calls 
a  thing — an  existence  placed  halfway  between  the  '  thing  ' 
and  the  '  representation  '  "  (p.  vii.). 

The  distinction  which  Bergson  has  in  mind  in  the  above 
is  not,  I  think,  the  distinction  between  the  imaging  as  a 
mental  occurrence  and  the  thing  imaged  as  an  object.  He 
is  th' nking  of  the  distinction  between  the  thing  as  it  is  and 
the  thing  as  it  appears,  neither  of  which  belongs  to  the  subject . 
Tne  distinction  between  subject  and  object,  between  the 
mind  which  thinks  and  remembers  and  has  images  on  the  one 
hand,  and  the  objects  thought  about,  remembered,  or  imaged — 
this  distinction,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  is  wholly  absent  from  his 
philosophy.  Its  absence  is  his  real  debt  to  idealism ;  and  a 
very  unfortunate  debt  it  is.  In  the  case  of  "  images,"  as 
we  have  just  seen,  it  enables  him  first  to  speak  of  images  as 
neutral  between  mind  and  matter,  then  to  assert  that  the 
brain  is  an  image  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  it  has  never  been 
imaged,  then  to  suggest  that  matter  and  the  perception  of 
matter  are  the  same  tring,  but  that  a  non-perceived  image 
(such  as  the  brain)  is  an  unconscious  mental  state  ;  while 
finally,  the  use  of  the  word  "  image,"  though  involving  no 
metaphysical  theories  whatever,  nevertheless  implies  that 
every  reality  has  "  a  kinship,  an  analogy,  in  short  a  relation  " 
with  consciousness. 

All  these  confusions  are  due  to  the  initial  confusion  of 
subject  and  object.  The  subject — a  thought  or  an  image 
or  a  memory — is  a  present  fact  in  me  ;  the  object  may  be  the 
law  of  gravitation  or  my  friend  Jones  or  the  o'd  Campanile 
of  Venice.     The  subject  is  mental  and  is  here  and  now.  There- 


24 

fore,  if  subject  and  object  are  one,  the  object  is  mental  and 
is  here  and  now  ;  my  friend  Jones,  though  he  believes  himself 
to  be  in  South  America  and  to  exist  on  his  own  account,  is 
really  in  my  head  and  exists  in  virtue  of  my  thinking  about 
him  ;  St.  Mark's  Campanile,  in  spite  of  its  great  size  and  the 
fact  that  it  ceased  to  exist  ten  years  ago,  still  exists,  and  is 
to  be  found  complete  inside  me.  These  statements  are  no 
travesty  of  Bergson's  theories  of  space  and  time  ;  they  are 
merely  an  attempt  to  show  what  is  the  actual  concrete  meaning 
of  those  theories. 

The  confusion  of  subject  and  object  is  not  peculiar  to 
Bergson,  but  is  common  to  many  idealists  and  many 
materialists.  Many  idealists  say  that  the  object  is  really 
the  subject,  and  many  materialists  say  that  the  subject  is 
really  the  object.  They  agree  in  thinking  these  two  state- 
ments very  different,  while  yet  holding  that  subject  and  object 
are  not  different.  In  this  respect,  we  may  admit,  Bergson 
has  merit,  for  he  is  as  ready  impartially  to  identify  subject 
with  object  as  to  identify  object  with  subject.  As  soon  as 
this  identification  is  rejected,  his  whole  system  collapses  : 
first  his  theories  of  space  and  time,  then  his  belief  in  real 
contingency,  then  his  condemnation  of  intellect,  then  his 
account  of  the  relations  of  mind  and  matter,  and  last  of  all 
his  whole  view  that  the  universe  contains  no  things,  but  only 
actions,  movements,  changes,  from  nothing  to  nothing,  in 
an  endless  alternation  of  up  and  down. 

Of  course  a  large  part  of  Bergson's  philosophy,  probably 
the  part  to  which  most  of  its  popularity  is  due,  does  not 
depend  upon  argument,  and  cannot  be  upset  by  argument. 
His  imaginative  picture  of  the  world,  regarded  as  a  poetic 
effort,  is  in  fne  main  not  capable  of  either  proof  or  disproof. 
Shakespeare  says  life's  but  a  walking  shadow,  Shelley  says 
it  is  like  a  dome  of  many  coloured  glass,  Bergson  says  it  is  a 
shell  which  bursts  into  parts  that  are  again  shells.  If  you 
like  Bergson's  image  better,  it  is  just  as  legitimate. 

The  good  which  Bergson  hopes  to  see  realised  in  the 
world  is  action  for  the  sake  of  action.     All  pure  contemplation 


25 

he  calls  "  dreaming,"  and  condemns  by  a  whole  seiies  of 
uncomplimentary  epithets  :  static,  Platonic,  mathematical, 
logical,  intellectual.  Those  who  desire  some  prevision  of 
the  end  which  action  is  to  achieve  are  told  that  an  end  foieseen 
would  be  nothing  new,  because  desire,  like  memory,  is  identified 
with  its  object.  Thus  we  are  condemned,  in  action,  to  be  the 
blind  slaves  of  instinct  :  the  life-force  pushes  us  on  from 
behind,  restlessly  and  unceasingly.  There  is  no  room  in  this 
philosophy  for  the  moment  of  contemplative  insight  when, 
lising  above  the  animal  life,  we  become  conscious  of  the 
greater  ends  that  redeem  man  from  the  life  of  the  brutes. 
Those  to  whom  activity  without  purpose  seems  a  sufficient 
good  will  find  in  Bergson's  books  a  pleasing  picture  of  the 
univeis  .  But  those  to  whom  action,  if  it  is  to  be  of  any  value, 
must  be  inspired  by  some  vision,  by  some  imaginative  foie- 
shadowing  of  a  world  less  painful,  less  unjust,  less  full  of 
strife  than  the  world  of  our  e/ery-day  fife,  those,  in  a  word, 
whose  action  is  built  on  contemplation,  will  find  in  this 
philosophy  nothing  of  what  they  seek,  and  will  not  regret 
that  tnere  is  no  reason  to  think  it  tiue. 


26 


ON    MR.    RUSSELLS   REASONS  FOR 

SUPPOSING    THAT    BERGSON'S 

PHILOSOPHY  IS  NOT  TRUE. 


BY  H.   WILDON    CARR. 


In  his  criticism  of  Bergson,  Mr.  Russell  begins  by 
giving  a  description  of  Bergson's  philosophy  which  presents 
the  leading  features  of  the  doctrine,  with  certain  ironical 
touches  such  as  we  expect  from  "  a  cool  ciitic,  who  feels  himself 
a  spectator,  perhaps  an  unsympathetic  spectator,"  and  con- 
cludes with  the  opinion  that  there  is  no  reason  whatever  for 
accepting  it,  either  in  the  universe  or  in  the  writings  of  Mr. 
Bergson.  Had  Mr.  Russell  ended  his  paper  with  this  negative 
conclusion,  he  would  have  thrown  on  the  champion  of  Bergson, 
willing  to  take  up  the  challenge,  the  formidable  task  of  dis- 
covering a  reason  that  would  oblige  the  critic  to  modify  his 
attitude,  but  fortunately  in  the  second  part  of  his  paper  he 
has  given  us  two  reasons  for  rejecting  the  philosophy.  It  is 
these  two  reasons  that  seem  to  me  to  demand  careful  examina  - 
tion  and  reply. 

The  two  reasons  are  directed  against  the  two  foundations 
of  Bergson's  philosophy,  the  doctrines  of  space  and  of  time. 
In  singling  out  these  points  for  nis  attack,  Mr.  Russell  has 
shown  something  like  the  anatomical  skill  of  the  paralysing 
wasp  in  one  of  Bergson's  best  known  illustrations  ;  if  the 
argument  gets  home,  it  will  destroy  all  power  for  harm  the 
philosophy  may  have  without  killing  it  outright,  for  Mr. 
Russell  is  willing  to  leave  us  its  poetry. 

The  first  argument  is  directed  against  the  well  known  and 
fundamental  doctrine  that  the  intellect  is  a  mode  of  activity 
whose  essential  function  is  to  spatialise  reality.  Whatever 
the  object  trat  we  apprehend  intellectually,  becomes  in  such 


27 

intellectual  apprehension  an  extended  image.  Mr.  Russell  ' 
takes  the  particular  instance  of  number  and  proceeds  to  prove 
that  Bergson  does  not  know  what  number  is,  and  has  himself 
no  clear  idea  of  it.  Three  entirely  different  things  are  con- 
fused, he  tells  us,  in  Bergson's  account,  namely,  (i)  number. 
the  general  concept  applicable  to  the  various  particular 
numbers,  (2)  the  various  particular  numbers  and  (3)  the 
various  collections  to  which  the  various  particular  numbers 
are  applicable.  When,  therefore,  Bergson  says  that  "  as 
soon  as  we  wish  to  picture  number  to  ourselves  and  not  merely 
figures  01  words,  we  are  compelled  to  have  recourse  to  an 
extended  image,"  this  can  only  refer  to  meaning  (3)  and  to 
assert  it  of  (1)  or  (2)  shows  a  failure  to  appreciate  a  vital 
distinction. 

Before  I  attempt  to  reply  to  this  argument,  let  me  clear 
the  ground  by  examining  a  suggested  explanation  that 
Mr.  Russell  offers  of  the  reason  why  Bergson  may  have  failed 
to  understand  this  distinction,  a  reason  of  a  personal  and 
psychological  nature,  namely,  that  Bergson  is  a  visualizer. 
Mr.  Russell  makes  a  great  point  of  this.  He  suggests  it  first 
of  all  in  his  general  survey  and  then  returns  to  it  as  something 
illustrate  1  and  demonstrated  by  this  very  case  in  point.  When 
Mr.  Russell  says  that  Bergson  is  a  visualizer  he  seems,  indeed, 
to  suggest  that  to  be  a  visualizer  is  to  suffer  from  a  defect 
which  distinctly  handicaps  the  patient.  We  may  be  quite 
sure  that  Mr.  Russell  intends  nothing  of  the  kind  if  he  did 
we  should  be  driven  to  suppose  that  he  consideied  the  only 
pei  son  capable  of  pure  appreciation  of  philosophical  distinc- 
tions is  the  man  blind  from  his  birth.  Psychologists  divide 
us  all,  I  believe,  according  to  the  prevailing  character  of  our 
mental  imagery,  according  to  whether  it  is  prevailingly  visual, 
auditory  or  motor,  and  it  is  found  that  we  diffei  from  one 
another  very  considerably  in  this  respect,  but  I  do  not  know 
that  it  has  ever  been  alleged  that  one  form  of  imagery  rather 
than  another  either  gives  an  intellectual  advantage  or  con- 
stitutes an  intellectual  defect.  But  whether  that  is  so  or  no' , 
anyone  who  has  the  psychological  habit  of  introspection  can 


28 


test  for  himself  the  prevailing  character  of  his  imagery  and 
so  can  know  whether  he  is  or  is  not  a  visualizer,  and  if  that 
is  so  I  can  settle  the  question  finally  so  far  as  Bergson  is 
concerned,  for  I  have  learnt  on  his  own  authority  that  he  is 
not. 

Of  the  meanings  of  number,  Mr.  Russell  allows  that 
Bergson's  doctrine  that  intellectual  apprehension  compels 
us  to  have  recourse  to  an  extended  image  is  true  of  meaning 
(3)  but  denies  tnat  it  is  true  of  meanings  (1)  and  (2).  Here 
then  is  a  clear  issue.  It  is  important  to  note  that  Bergson 
himself  in  the  sentence  criticised  makes  a  distinction  "  As 
soon  as  we  wish  to  picture  number  and  not  merely  figures  or 
words."  The  italics  are  Bergson's.  This  is  important 
because  it  admits  that  we  can,  and  ordinarily  do,  apprehend 
meanings  by  figures  or  wor  is  and  these  do  not  compel  recourse 
to  an  extended  image.  "  It  is  the  clear  idea  of  number  that 
implies  a  visual  image  in  space."  It  does  not  seem  to  me 
material  to  the  argument  that  the  image  should  be  visual  as 
distinct  from  auditory  or  motor,  the  essential  thing  is  that 
it  is  spatial.  It  should  be  borne  in  mind  that  Bergson  uses 
the  word  image  for  what  Mr.  Russell  calls  a  sense  datum  and 
other  pnilosophers  a  presentation  ;  and  perhaps  the  greatest 
disadvantage  of  Bergson's  term  is  that  it  suggests  something 
exclusively  visual.  Now  Mr.  Russell  has  arranged  his  three 
meanings  in  a  certain  order, — is  this  oider  also  an  order  of 
knowing  ?  To  be  more  precise,  does  Mr.  Russell  hold  that 
we  can  be  acquainted  with  meaning  (1)  while  totally  un- 
acquainted with  meaning  (2)  ?  and  meaning  (2)  while 
unacquainted  with  meaning  (3).  Let  us  see.  Mr.  Russell 
holds  tnat  we  know  universals  and  sense  data  by  acquaintance, 
and  also  that  the  universal  is  an  object  of  knowledge  quite 
distinct  from  particular  instances.  Thus  the  number  12  is 
a  universal  known  by  acquaintance,  it  is  applicable  to  various 
particular  instances,  the  twelve  apostles,  twelve  tribes  of 
Israel,  &c,  none  of  which  instances  is  the  number  12,  but  the 
number  12  is  something  common  to  all  the  instances,  whether 
these  are  known  or  unknown,  actual  or  possible,  existent  or 


29 

non-existent.  Suppose  this  granted,  can  we  apprehend  the 
number  12  if  we  have  never  had  acquaintance  with  any 
particular  instance  of  12  units  ?  Cleat ly  Mr.  Russell's 
definition  shows  that  this  is  impossible,  and  that  there  can 
only  be  acquaintance  with  a  universal  if  there  has  already 
been  acquaintance  with  sense  data  which  are  particular,  for 
how  does  he  define  the  number  12  ?  "  The  number  12, 
obviously,"  he  says,  "  is  something  which  all  these  collections 
of  12  units  have  in  common."  Suppose  then  I  am  not 
acquainted  with  any  collection  of  12  units  clearly  I  cannot 
be  acquainted  with  that  which  is  common  to  all  collections 
of  12  units  ?  Granting  then  that  the  universal,  the  number 
12,  is  a  distinct  object  of  the  nund,  known  by  acquaintance, 
how  can  its  meaning  be  apprehended  except  as  "  a  synthesis 
of  the  one  and  many,"  and  how  can  a  synthesis  be  presented 
to  the  mind  except  by  recouise  to  an  extended  image  ?  But, 
says  Mr.  Russell,  "  we  cannot  picture  the  number  12  because 
it  is  something  more  abstract  than  any  picture."  No  doubt, 
but  to  admit  that  it  is  more  abstract  than  any  picture  is  not 
to  prove  that  we  apprenend  it  without  recourse  to  an  extended 
image.  Let  us  grant  that  the  abstract  12  "is  obviously 
conceivable  and  obviously  incapable  of  being  pictured  in 
space,"  we  have  still  to  acknowledge  that  this  abstract  12  is 
"  what  different  collections  of  12  units  have  in  common." 
We  may  not  picture  the  abstract  12  but  we  are  dependent 
on  an  extended  image  for  our  apprehension  of  its  meaning. 
Unless  therefore  Mr.  Russell  holds  that,  like  Condillac's 
statue  with  no  sense  but  that  of  smell,  there  might  exist  a 
mind  with  no  object  present  to  it  but  the  abstract  12,  I  for 
one  see  no  reason  in  his  argument  for  supposing  Bergson's 
doctrine  not  true. 

In  close  connection  with  this  argument  Mr.  Russell 
charges  Bergson  with  neglect  of  the  modern  views  of  mathe- 
matics. "  He  deliberately,"  he  says,  "  preferred  traditional 
errors  in  interpretation  to  the  more  modern  views  which  have 
prevailed  among  mathematicians  for  the  last  half  century." 
Now  I  am  not  qualified,  and  therefore  shall  not  presume  to 


30 

discuss  mathematical  theories  with  Mr.  Russell.  I  go  to  him  to 
learn  not  to  criticise.  I  will  look  at  this  charge  therefore 
from  the  standpoint  of  a  disinterested  spectator. 

The  case  in  point  is  Bergson's  solution  of  Zeno's  argument 
of  the  arrow.  According  to  Mr.  Russell,  modern  mathematics 
states  the  problem  in  terms  that  deprive  the  paradox  of 
meaning,  so  that  ZenoV  problem  no  longer  exists  and  Bergson's 
argument  to  meet  it  is  superfluous.  This,  Mr.  Russell  admits, 
is  Zeno's  fault,  not  Bergson's,  but  if  Bergson  had  familiarised 
himself  with  modern  mathematical  theory  he  would  not  have 
revived  the  ancient  puzzle.  Let  us  put  the  two  solutions  side 
by  side.  Bergson  says  that  Zeno  failed  to  see  that  a  move- 
ment is  indivisible,  you  can  only  divide  it  by  stopping  it, 
and  that  is  destroying  it,  not  dividing  it.  You  think  you  can 
divide  ic  because  you  measure  the  course  of  the  trajectory, 
and  that  being  spatial,  and  therefore  immobile,  is  divisible 
infinitely.  Modern  mathematics,  on  the  other  hand,  says 
that  continuity  is  infinite  divisibility,  that  is  to  say,  that  if 
there  is  an  infinite  number  between  any  two  numbers  in  a 
series,  so  that  there  is  no  next  number,  then  the  series  is 
continuous — this  is  all  that  continuity  can  mean.  "  A 
cinematograph,"  s;iys  Mi.  Russell,  "in  which  there  are  an 
mfinUe  number  of  films,  and  in  which  there  is  never  a  next 
film,  because  an  infinite  number  comes  bftween  any  two, 
will   perfectly   represent    a    continuous    motion."     Well,   ot 

e,  we  musl  admit  that,  if  we  accept  this  definition  of 
i  ratinuity  i  take-  away  the  ground  of  Zeno's  argument — 
bul  does  it  remove  the  paradox  in  the  idea  of  movement  ? 
Tiiis  is  the  kind  ot  difficulty  I  feel  in  regard  to  ;ill  Mr.  Russell's 
work,  he  removes  onep  ily  tole  ive  me  with  a  greater. 

If  I  am  puzzled  to  understand  how  Achilles  can  overtake 
the  tortoise,  Mr.  Russell  leaves  me  m  doubt  whether  I  can 
even  affirm  that  the  tortoise  cannof  overtake  Achilles,  [s 
there  not  a  one-to-one  relation  between  the  fast  stride  of 
Achilles  and  the  slow  step  of  the  tortoise,  so  that,  granted 
infinite  time,  eve  that   Achilles  lakes  will  be  takei 

by  ti. 


3i 

Bergson  may  be  right  or  he  may  be  wrong,  but  he  offers 
a  solution  of  a  paradox,  whereas  Mr.  Russell  offers  a  choice  of 
paradoxes.  I,  for  one,  can  find  no  reason  in  modern  views 
of  mathematics  for  supposing  the  Bergson's  solution  is  not 
true. 

I  now  come  to  the  second  fundamental  position  that 
Mr.  Russell  attacks,  namely,  Bergson's  theory  of  duiaticn. 
This  attack,  if  it  succeeds,  is  the  more  deadly  of  the  two. 
Here  again  it  is  a  confusion  of  two  things  that  are  quite  distinct 
that  is  charged  against  Bergson, — the  confusion  between  the 
act  of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known.  If  this  can  be 
brought  home  to  him  then  Mr.  Russell  tells  us  "  his  whole 
system  collapses  :  first  his  theories  of  space  and  time,  then 
his  belief  in  real  contingency,  then  his  condemnation  of  in- 
tellect, then  his  account  of  the  relation  of  mind  and  matter, 
and,  last  of  all,  his  whole  view  that  the  universe  contains  no 
things  but  only  actions,  movements,  cha.iges  from  nothing  to 
notning,  in  an  endless  alternation  of  up  and  down."  The 
phrase  "  nothing  to  nothing  "  in  this  quotation  ignores  the 
important  and  essential  doctrine  whicn  Bergson  insists  is 
fundamental  to  the  comprehension  of  his  view,  namely, 
that  nothing  is  a  pseudo-idea.  It  is  also  rather  curious  that 
Mr.  Russell  attributes  the  confusion  he  alleges  between  the 
act  of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known,  in  part  to  the  pro- 
found influence  of  Berkeley  01  Bergson's  thought,  whereas, 
Dr.  Dawes  Hicks,  who  has  made  the  same  criticism  of  Bergson, 
insists  that  this  veiy  distinction  is  clearly  remarked  by 
Berkeley  and  essential  to  the  Berkeleyan  view.  This  however 
by  the  way,  our  concern  is  to  know  if  Mr.  Russell's  charge  is 
true.  I  think  the  criticism  simply  rests  on  a  failure  to 
appreciate  the  exact  problem  that  Bergson  is  dealing  with 
in  his  doctrine  of  duration.  I  do  not  know  that  Bergson  has 
anywhere  distinctly  approached  the  problem  of  knowledge 
from  the  standpoint  of  what  Meinong  calls  Gegensiandstheorie. 
I  do  not  know  what  hr  view  on  that  problem  would  be  if  he 
did  give  attention  to  ic,  but  I  cannot  see  its  relevance  to  the 
actual  doctrine  of  duration.     The  distinction  between  the 


32 

act  of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known  is  surely  implicit, 
if  it  is  not  explicit,  in  all  that  Bergson  has  said  of  intellectual 
knowledge.  Has  not  Mr.  Russell  himself  called  our  attention 
in  this  paper  to  Bergson's  ultra-realist  position  in  regard  to 
perception  ?  How  is  a  confusion  between  subject  and  object 
consistent  with  any  realist  theory  ?  It  can  only  be  with 
regard  to  the  knowledge  that  Bergson  calls  intuition  that 
this  charge  of  confusion  can  have  any  semblance  of  meaning, 
and  there  so  far  from  the  identity  of  subject  and  object  being 
a  confusion  it  is  of  the  very  essence  of  the  doctrine.  Mr. 
Russell  is  perfectly  entitled  to  question  or  deny  that  we  can 
have  knowledge  by  intuition,  but  if  there  is  such  knowledge 
it  is  characterised  by  just  this  fact  that  it  is  consciousness  of 
life  in  living.  The  act  of  knowing  turns  inwards,  itself  knows 
its  knowing.  Now  we  are  all  ready  to  admit  that  such 
knowledge  is  rare  and  very  difficult,  and  Mr.  Russell  may  be 
right  if  he  holds  that  it  is  not  merely  difficult  but  impossible, 
but  he  has  no  right  to  charge  Bergson  with  confusing  two 
things  which  if  this  knowledge  exists  are  identical,  namely, 
tne  act  of  knowing  and  that  which  is  known. 

As  I  am  one  of  those  to  whom  not  the  poetry  but  only 
the  metaphysics  of  Bergson  makes  appeal,  I  am  glad  that  I  do 
not  find  in  either  of  Mr.  Russell's  reasons  a  reason  to  think 
that  this  philosophy  is  not  true. 


33 


MR.    WILDON   CARRS  DEFENCE  OF 
BERGSON. 

BY   THE    HON.    BERTRAND    RUSSELL. 


At  the  outset,  it  seems  necessary  to  clear  up  a  miscon- 
ception of  my  purpose.  I  did  not  attempt  to  prove  that 
"  Bergson's  pnilosophy  is  not  true,"  if  we  mean  by  h's 
philosophy  the  conclusions  at  which  he  arrives  rather  than  the 
reasons  which  he  gives  for  them.  The  conclusion  of  the  first 
part  of  my  paper,  quoted  by  Mr.  Carr,  is  that  "  there  is  no 
reason  whatever  for  accepting  this  view  "  ;  the  conclusion  of 
the  second  part  is  almost  verbally  the  same,  namely  "  that 
tnere  is  no  reason  to  think  it  true."  These  phrases  were 
intentional.  M.  Bergson's  philosophy,  like  all  othei  ambitious 
systems,  is  supported  by  arguments  which  I  believe  to  be 
fallacious,  but  it  does  not  follow  that  it  is  in  fact  false.  I 
hold  that  much  less  can  be  known  about  the  universe  as  a 
whole  than  many  philosophers  are  inclined  to  suppose  ;  I 
should  not  therefore  assert  dogmatically  that  the  universe 
is  other  than  it  is  said  to  be  in  this  or  that  system,  unless 
the  account  in  question  appeared  self-contradictory.  What 
I  do  maintain  is  that,  in  view  of  the  mistakes  in  Bergson's 
reasoning,  bis  conclusions  remain  mere  imaginative  possibilities 
to  be  placed  alongside  of  the  thousand  other  possibilities 
invented  by  cosmic  poets. 

Mr.  Carr,  however,  in  spite  of  an  apparent  concession  in 
in  his  first  paragraph,  proceeds  to  defend  Bergson's  arguments  ; 
and  we  must  therefore  proceed  to  examine  his  defence.  In 
supposing  Bergson  to  be  a  visualizer,  it  appears  1  was  mistaken, 
but   the  important  point  remains,   that   h;s  speculation  is 


34 

dominated  by  the  sense  of  sight  to  a  remarkable  pxtent,  and 
that  this  seems  connected  with  the  importance  which  he 
assigns  to  space. 

Mr.  Carr  next  considers  the  distinction  which  I  emphasize 
between  (i)  the  general  concept  Number,  (2)  the  particular 
numbers,  (3)  the  various  collections  to  which  numbers  are 
applicable.  He  says  I  allow  "  that  Bergson's  doctrine  that 
intellectual  apprehension  compels  us  to  have  recourse  to  atr 
extended  image  is  true  of  meaning  (3)."  This  is  a  misunder- 
standing ;  the  view  in  question  is  examined  and  rejected  in 
the  paragraph  on  p.  15  beginning  "  But  apart  from  the 
question  of  numbers,  shall  we  admit  Bergson's  contention 
that  every  plurality  of  separate  units  involves  space  ?  "  Hence 
the  inferences  drawn  by  Mr.  Carr  from  my  supposed  concession 
fall  to  the  ground. 

The  next  question  raised,  as  to  the  order  in  which  we 
come  to  know  the  above  three  meanings,  appears  to  me 
logically  irrelevant,  and  it  is  only  under  protest  that  I  am 
willing  to  consider  it.  He  asks  :  "  Can  we  apprehend  the 
number  12  if  we  have  never  had  acquaintance  with  any 
particular  instance  of  12  units  ?  "  He  supposes  that  my 
answer  must  be  in  the  negative,  because  I  say  that  the  number 
12  is  "  something  which  all  these  collections  of  12  units  have 
in  common,"  and  he  supposes  that  this  is  a  definition  of  12. 
It  is  not  a  definition,  and  does  not  have  the  form  of  a  definition. 
And  I  certainly  hold  that  we  might  appiehend  the  number  12 
without  having  acquaintance  with  any  particular  dozen.  I 
have  not,  so  far  as  I  know,  ever  been  acquainted  with  a 
collection  of  34,361  units,  yet  I  apprehend  the  number  34,361. 
But  it  is  impossible  to  pursue  this  topic  without  raising  the 
whole  question  of  our  acquaintance  with  universals. 

With  regard  to  Zeno,  Mr.  Carr  says  that  I  remove  one 
paradox  only  to  leave  him  with  a  greater.  I  admit  that  this 
impression  is  partly  my  fault,  and  that  I  have  not  always 
been  sufficiently  careful  to  display  my  slavish  adherence 
to  common  sense.  But  in  the  main  the  impiession — which 
Mr.  Carr  shares  with  many  philosophers  who  have  tried  to 


35 

understand  the  mathematical  theory  of  infinity  and  con- 
tinuity— is  due  to  the  almost  unconscious  drawing  of  fallacious 
inferences.  For  instance,  if  I  say  "  no  part  of  Tristram 
Shandy's  biography  would  remain  permanently  unwritten," 
I?m  supposed  to  imply  that  some  day  the  biography  will  be 
finished,  which  is  by  no  means  implied,  and  in  the  circum- 
stances supposed  is  plainly  false.  This  applies  to  Mr.  Carr's 
doubt  whether,  on  my  principles,  the  tortoise  cannot  overtake 
Achilles.  I  say  that,  if  they  go  on  for  ever,  every  place 
reached  by  Achilles  will  ultimately  be  reached  by  the  tortoise  ; 
?nd  at  first  sight  this  seems  inconsistent  with  the  statement 
that,  after  Achilles  has  passed  the  tortoise,  the  distance 
between  them  will  continually  increase.  But  this  apparent 
inconsistency  disappears  as  soon  as  the  matter  is  understood. 

With  regard  to  the  phrase  "  from  nothing  to  nothing," 
Mr.  Carr  says  I  ignore  Bergson's  doctrine  that  "  nothing  "  is 
a  pseudo-idea.  This  is  a  misunderstanding.  I  hold  just  as 
strongly  as  Bergson  (though  for  different  reasons)  that 
"  nothing  "  is  a  pseudo-idea  ;  I  used  the  phrase,  as  it  ordinarily 
would  be  used,  as  an  abbreviation  for  the  phrase  "  not  from 
anything  and  not  to  anything. 

Witn  regard  to  the  confusion  of  subject  and  object  with 
which  I  charge  Bergson,  Mi.  Can  says  that  as  regards  in- 
tuition "  so  far  from  the  identity  of  subject  and  object  being 
a  confusion,  it  is  of  the  very  essence  of  the  doctrine."  It  was 
precisely  my  contention  that  it  was  of  the  essence  of  the 
doctrine  ;  but  I  fail  to  see  how  this  proves  that  it  is  not  a 
confusion.  It  seems  to  me  that  only  one  who  has  never 
clearly  distinguished  subject  and  object  can  accept  Bergson's 
"  intuition."  In  the  case  of  memory,  this  seems  particularly 
evident,  since  it  becomes  necessary  for  Bergson  to  identify 
remembering  with  what  is  remembered,  and  therefore  to  say 
that  whatever  is  remembered  still  endures.  To  say  that  such 
identification  is  of  the  essence  of  nis  doctrine  is  no  defence ; 
the  only  valid  defence  would  be  to  show  that  remembering 
is  in  fact  identical  with  what  is  remembered. 


36 


In  conclusion,  I  must  admit  that  there  is  an  element  of 

question-begging  in  all  refutations  of  Bergson.  When  we  have 
shown  that  this  or  that  doctrine  is  self-contradictory,  we  have 
only  shown  that  it  does  not  appeal  to  the  intellect ;  if  the 
intellect  is  in  fact  misleading,  as  Bergson  contends,  it  is 
useless  to  employ  it  against  him.  It  is  true  that  Bergson 
continually  employs  it  in  his  own  defence,  by  advancing 
arguments  which  plainly  are  intended  to  be  intellectually 
satisfying.  But  this  perhaps  is  a  concession  to  the  uncon- 
verted :  when  his  philosophy  has  triumphed,  it  is  to  be  sup- 
posed that  argument  will  cease,  and  intellect  will  be  lulled 
to  sleep  on  the  heaving  sea  of  intuition.  But  until  that 
consummation  the  protests  of  intellect  will  continue. 


KXPRE3S  PRINTING  WORKS,    36,  KING  STREET,  CAMBRIDGE. 


The  following  addresses  delivered  before  the  Society  have 
also  been  published  in  pamphlet  form  and  may  be  obtained 
from  any  Cambridge  bookseller,  or  from  the  Secretary  : — 

Dare  to  be  Wise,  by  Dr.  J.  E.  McTaggart. 

Heresy  and  Humanity,  by  Miss  J.  E.  Harrison. 

The  Future  of  Religion,  by  G.  Bernard  Shaw. 

A  Reply  to  Mr.  Shaw,  by  G.  K.  Chesterton. 

Religion  in  the  University,  by  F.  M.  Cornford. 

Modem  Morality  and  Modern  Toleration,  by  E.  S.  P.  Haynes. 

Unanimism,  by  Miss  J.  E.  Harrison. 

De  Haeretico  Comburendo,  by  G.  M.  Trevelyan. 

The  Historicity  of  Jesus,  being  a  debate  on  the  Christ-Myth 
Controversy  between  J.  M.  Robertson,  M.P.,  and  H.  G. 
Wood,  M.A. 


In  addition,  the  following  papers  read  before  the  Society 
have  been  printed  in  periodicals  : — 

The  Primitive  Conception  of  Death,  by  Dr.  W.  H.  R.  Rivers. 
(Hibbert  Journal,  1912). 

The  Problem  of  an  Effective  Lay  Moral  Education,  by  Harrold 
Johnson  (International  Journal  of  Ethics,  1912). 

The  Creation  of  Taste,  by  Holbrook  Jackson  (English  Review, 

19*3)- 


Some  particulars  of  the  Society  will  be  found  on  the  following 
page. 


HONORARY  MEMBERS. 


Prof.  E.  G.  Browne. 

E.  Bullough. 
Prof.  J.  B.  Bury. 
G.  G.  Chisholm. 

F.  M.  Cornford. 

Sir  Francis  Darwin. 
E.  J.  Dent. 

G.  Lowes  Dickinson. 
Prof.  Arthur  Drews. 
Prof.   Patrick  Geddes. 
Prof.  H.  A.  Giles. 

L.  H.  G.  Greenwood. 

Dr.  A.  C.  Haddon. 

Prof.  E.  W.  Hobson. 

G.  H.  Hardy. 

Miss  J.  E.  Harrison. 

Professor  L.  T.  Hobhouse. 

W.  E.  Johnson. 

J.  M.  Keynes. 

W.  R.  M.  Lamb. 

Dr.  J.  E.  McTaggart. 

Dr.  W.  McDougall. 

Prof.  H.  O.  Meredith. 


G.  E.' Moore. 

V.    H.    MOTTRAM. 

Dr.  F.  Muller-Lyer. 
Dr.  C.  S.  Myers. 
Prof.  R.  C.  Punnett. 
Dr.  W.  H.  Rivers. 

D.  S.  Robertson. 
Dr.  G.  F.  Rogers. 

The  Hon.  Bertrand  Russell. 

Miss  E.  Sargant. 

Prof.  A.  C.  Seward. 

G.  Bernard  Shaw. 

J.  T.  Sheppard. 

Miss  F.  M.  Stawell. 

Prof.  G.  F.  Stout. 

F. J. M.  Stratton 

H.  W.  V.  Temperley. 

G.  M.  Trevelyan. 

Prof.  W.  F.  Trotter. 

Dr.  Ivor  Tuckett. 

V.  S.  Vernon  Jones. 

E.  Vulliamy. 

H.  J.  Wolstenholme. 


COMMITTEE. 


President  : 
C.  K.  Ogden  (Magdalene  College). 

Treasurer  : 
W.  L.  Scott  (Clare  College). 

Secretary  : 
P.  Sargant  Florence 

(Caius  College). 


A.  S.  Florence  (Newnham 

College). 

C.  Thorne  (Clare  College). 
H.  B.  Usher  (Trinity  Hall). 
A.  L.  Gardiner  (Caius  College). 


EXTRACT  FROM  THE  LAWS. 

2.     That  the  object  of  the  Society  be  to  promote  discussion  on 
problems  of  Religion,  Philosophy,  and  Art. 

4.     Membership  of  the  Society  shall  imply  the  rejection  of  all 
appeal  to  Authority  in  the  discussion  of  religious  questions. 


. 


I  MVLRSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA   LIBRARY 
Los  Angeles 

This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


-  — 


. 


u 


fftrc 


DISCHARGE-URL 


NOV 

KtCU  LO-Uffl 

APR     91380 

p 


«,: ,  um«  : 


,*<y0  U>«* 


DEC  1 6  1991 


Ql 


33 


J  3  1979  0[QCri 


KEO'D  LD-U 


mioN 


^;*.^ 


,  OCT  27  '89 


ONE 


JUN   2198Q. 


Form  L9-Series4939 


9  iSf  f  AUG  2 1  199 
w29^     JUL30199S 


■    '*£ 


ii  ii  nun  mi  mi  mi  mi  ii  nil  mm  \\ 

3  1158  00514  8712 


UC  SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY